Used price: $2.22
Collectible price: $14.82
Used price: $20.00
Collectible price: $15.88
La Razon de Mi vida or My Mission in Life as it was translated into english, was meant to be an autobiography of perhaps the strongest and most influential woman of the XX century, many strong women have come and go but none have left such lasting impression like Evita has, perhaps the other one would be her alter ego in a movie, Madonna.
The book doesn't tell us anything about her origins but it does tell us where she wants to go, it's a true insight of her vision, her leadership and the strong love and devotion she felt for her husband.
It is more of a political and love statement than anything else, it's the pure and raw Evita, this is her essence and what made her who she was and who she is.
Used price: $22.43
Buy one from zShops for: $95.00
having most of the these dishes as a child.
The only way I ever knew the recipes was by calling
my Mom or my Grandma, a province away, to ask what I
needed to complete a dish I relished as a child.
What a pleasant surprise to find a cookbook that had
everything I ever remembered. Some of the recipes
are identical to ones I have scratched down on pieces
of scrap paper
Thank you to the author for such an easy book to follow.
Born in Hungary, she now lives in Canada. She and her husband John travel back regularly and her recipes are more correctly a blend of both traditional methods and current Hungarian cooking. I have tried a number of her recipes and they always work. I recommend her Langos, Roast Pork stuffed with Sausage (sometimes referred to as "in the manner of Debrecen"), and her Mock Venison. This is a worthwhile addition to any collection of Hungarian cookbooks. It is also an excellent value.
Used price: $7.40
Collectible price: $7.41
Buy one from zShops for: $11.22
List price: $12.95 (that's 20% off!)
Used price: $8.95
Buy one from zShops for: $9.50
I highly recommend this book for the world traveller, even if you're just going to Europe. You may be surprised at how useful it is!
List price: $12.95 (that's 20% off!)
Used price: $7.77
Collectible price: $32.50
Buy one from zShops for: $8.95
The original was written in the mid 1930s. As Klein writes in this version's preface, "This study was originally written and published in Germany during rather turbulent times."
The late Jacob Klein spent his post war years teaching Platonic philosophy at St. John's College. There, he was known as something of a lovable elitist. Professors tell a story about Klein being partial to the number 12. He claimed that there were an exclusive 12 philosophers, 7 Greek and 5 German. The word got out and he soon received a letter from 4,000 American philosophers begging to differ with his opinion.
While many might call this book 'philosophy of math,' I doubt Dr. Klein would agree. The book is without much in the way of serious math. It is more concerned with the symbols of math and how they are used. Quoting from the first paragraph of the introduction:
"Creation of a formal mathematical language was of decisive significance for the constitution of modern mathematical physics. If the mathematical presentation is regarded as a mere device, preferred only because the insights of natural science can be expressed by "symbols" in the simplest and most exact manner possible, the meaning of the symbolism as well as of the special methods of the physical disciplines in general will be misunderstood. True, in the seventeenth and eighteenth century it was still possible to' express and communicate discoveries concerning the "natural" relations of objects in non mathematical terms, yet even then -or, rather, particularly then - it was precisely the mathematical form, the mos geometricus, which secured their dependability and trustworthiness. After three centuries of intensive development, it has finally become impossible to separate the content of mathematical physics from its form. The fact that elementary presentations of physical science which are to a certain degree nonmathematical and appear quite free of presuppositions in their derivations of fundamental concepts (having recourse, throughout, to immediate "Intuition") are still in vogue should not deceive us about the fact that it is impossible, and has always been impossible, to grasp the meaning of what we nowadays call physics independently of its mathematical form. Thence arise the insurmountable difficulties in which discussions of modern physical theories become entangled as soon as physicist or nonphysicists attempt to disregard the mathematical apparatus and to present the results of scientific research in popular form. The intimate connection of the formal mathematical language with the content of mathematical physics stems from the special kind of conceptualization which is a concomitant of modern science and which was of fundamental importance in its formation."
While this iconoclastic promise is a bit difficult to extract from the somewhat professional philosophic prose, there is a wonderful essay in "Biographies of Scientific Objects," edited by Lorraine Daston that serves as an excellent commentary. The essay called "Mathematical Entities in Scientific Discourse" credits Klein with a new perspective from which to interpret the transition of ancient and medieval traditions to the new mathematical physics of the seventeenth century. His was the seemingly narrow-but only deceptively so-perspective of the ancient concept of "arithmos", compared to the concept of number in its modern, symbolic sense. In Klein's own words, the underlying thematics of the book never loses sight of the "general transformation, closely connected with the symbolic understanding of number, of the scientific consciousness of later centuries."
Although the Greek conceptualization of mathematical objects was indeed based upon the notion of arithmos, this notion should not be thought of as a concept of "general magnitude." It never means anything other than "a definite number of definite objects," or an "assemblage of things counted". Likewise, geometric figures and curves, commensurable and incommensurable magnitudes, ratios, have their own special ontology which directs mathematical inquiry and its methods.
In contradistinction to Greek parlance, "general magnitude," according to Klein, is clearly a modern concept. Proving this case is the project of both books.
I think you will find reading this material an interesting journey.