Used price: $9.90
Buy one from zShops for: $16.75
Used price: $25.00
Used price: $24.95
Used price: $19.95
I spent some time checking out the claims of this book--which, in brief, are that the mature Strauss was a covert Nietzschean nihilist who believed in a politically significant order of rank among men--and I was totally unconvinced. If you're going to argue that a man secretly harbored beliefs directly at odds with ideas he dedicated 30 years of his life to advancing, you have to make a better case than this.
Similar things have been written about Strauss and Machiavelli, and they are similarly unbelievable. Memo to would-be esotericists: the device is almost never used directly to contradict a surface argument. Rather, it is used to conceal, while at the same pointing to, the deepest implications of that argument.
Nonetheless, I give this book two stars because it is not deviod of insight into Nietszche.
Lampert's work is a thorough and insightful reading of Strauss's essay "Note on the Plan of Nietzsche's 'Beyond Good and Evil'." Lampert's approach is definitely more Nietzchean than Straussian, which is to say it is not as nuanced or sufficiently ambiguous as Straussians--especially of the theistic flavor--like. But it is in a word outstanding and will hopefully embolden a few of Struass's more reticent students to step out of the shadows and into the Noon sunlight, in more Zarathustrian fashion.
This is what Lampert does, using a 17 page essay called "Not on the Plan of Nietzsche's Beyond Good and Evil", in Strauss' "Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy". Lampert eventually accumulates a significant argument in favor of his two theses, namely, that Strauss was a covert Nietzschean who felt that he could not speak aloud what he himself believed and who therefore took cover under the traditional garb of a philosopher (which both Nietzsche and Strauss took to be the cassock of a priest); and that Strauss himself is the best interpreter of Nietzsche the world has yet seen. Anyone who is interested in either man should read this book. It will provide a powerful incentive to rethink stereotypes about both men and their works, and it gives a fine summary of what Nietzsche actually was trying to communicate.
Used price: $17.98
List price: $14.29 (that's 20% off!)
Collectible price: $16.45
I found his reasoning to be rather bizarre. It seemed to be that he was using Nazism agains Nazis, which, as far as the bottom line goes, is still Nazism. That the movie and the comic book are seriously popular I chocked up to people liking far-out stories without much intellectual foundation.
Then I heard about Strauss. I haven't read the man. I probably never will. There's too many other esoteric philosophers influenced by Heidegger for me to read that I find more congenial to my tastes. But he literally is Magneto. What was the lesson Strauss learned from Nazi death camps? That they were run by the wrong people. If the Nazi party had been run by Jews who love ancient Greek philosophy more than they love the Bible, Nazi Germany would have been A-OK.
And that seriously begs credulity.
The first time I heard of Leo Strauss, it was while reading Dionne's _Why Americans Hate Politics_. Strauss was mentioned as a major philosophical influence behind neoconservatism (the anti-communist liberals who believed in virtue and rebelled against the new left in the 1960s). Dionne mentioned Alan Bloom's _Closing of the American Mind_ as an important work directly influenced by Strauss. After reading _Closing_ (and I must say, being blown away by the truth of it) I knew that I had to read Strauss for myself.
Natural Right and History is everything I wanted it to be. It starts with the modern day rejection of natural right, and it's consequences. Historicism (as well as the value relativism inherent in the social sciences) are exposed for what they are; self contradictory. The book goes on to trace the origin of natural right, and even philosophy itself, by examining the moment that the first philosopher questioned authority and asked the question "what is good?" by nature, as opposed to "what is good?" by convention. From the ancients to the moderns, every step in the development of natural right is traced, and the crisis of modern natural right is analyzed in fine detail.
I cannot recommend this book highly enough. It should appeal to anyone with a vested interest in America, particularly those with an interest in political philosophy. Dionne, and others, may give credit to Strauss for giving conservatives credibility in intellectual circles, but make no mistake; Strauss himself rises far above partisanship. He is a philosopher in the truest sense.
Strauss gave these lectures to counter what then was called historicism, the position that, because conceptions of such things as freedom and right have been so varied throughout time, that because nobody has been able to agree on what right is, that right is relative to the time. The upshod of the arguement is then, since nothing can count as right definitively, there is no right. Strauss argues that historicism, by being another appearance in history, is subject to the same criticism (therefore interally inconsistent) and that even if nobody has been able to agree on "right" doesn't mean that there isn't any such thing, but because debate has been so heated on the subject, it is only all the more evident that there is such a thing such as right.
I may be a slightly biased source, but i've read my share of Levi-Strauss and Foucault. Sure, Strauss confines himself to political philosophy, but the larger issues are there. Postmodern thought is showing strains of its own now, and Strauss pointed them out before they realized they were postmodern. Essential reading for both camps.
Used price: $21.67
Buy one from zShops for: $21.67
Drury may be called a popular corrupter by some (indeed, the repetitious writing leaves a thing to be desired), but this book is an honest survey of Straussian Philosophy and Classical Liberal Democracy, in the sense that the book contrasts Strauss's ideas against the backdrop of his enemy, classical liberal democracy. It is true that many modern conservatives (but usually not libertarians) may take offense to Classical Liberal Democracy, but so do modern liberal democrats. To illustrate this, allow me to give two examples and one comment: (1) Modern Liberals may be disturbed that the source of MODERN governmental welfare may not be Marx or, even, Enlightenment Liberalism, but the European conservative political ideologues of the 19th century--for example, Bismarck. (2) Likewise, American Conservatives may wince at the idea that they are really a new breed of ideologue who are only distantly related to the European Conservative Tradition and who have, instead, adopted the ideas of late 19th Century Social Darwinism and 20th Century nationalism. Modern Libertarians, on the other hand, may nod their heads to Drury acknowledging the bastardized lineage of both modern liberals and neo-conservatives, although ultimately Drury drops hints of an affinity for modern liberalism.
As one may see, Drury's descriptions and conclusions may disturb many modern political ideologues. Consequently, Drury's book is a valuable, although not unprecedented, contribution to the American canon; however, it may face opposition from modern liberals and neo-conservatives.
According to Drury, Strauss's philosophy accepts the death of God, (unlike traditional conservatism) and then moves positivistically (unlike traditional conservatism) to fill the vacuum with elite group of self-elected philosopher kings. This elite, alive to the nihilism of the liberal ethos and its potentially anarchic consequences, believes it must act forcefully to paper over the hole left by His demise. Their esoteric/exoteric readings of philosophy tell them they must forge from the ashes a seamless, monocultural machine to encourage obedience and staunch chaos. This nationalistic machine must be equipped with a religion (any religion) and a mythic culture based on flag-reverence and knee-jerk patriotism. This is necessary because pluralistic, liberal societies cannot meet the challenge posed by well-organized, culturally cohesive states. Because the mass of men are primitive, credulous, prone to error and evil, the state with the best machine necessarily will win. Straussians, unlike traditional conservatives who see the state as malevolent, justify their activism by insisting that as philosophers they are immune to temptations of power.
According to Drury, a particularly striking strategy of Straussian conservatives is their struggle to identify and mythologize American traditions. She points out that while Burke had the last remnants of feudalism to extol as a naturally just system, American conservatives have been forced to create a "traditional" America out of whole cloth. To do so, according the Drury, Strauss's followers have invaded history departments across the US where they have been working hard to uncover "tradition" in the beginnings of America - a difficult task given that America was the first truly modernist state. Nevertheless, these historians, depending upon which ax they are grinding, rewrite American history either to prove that colonial America was feudal, or to prove the Founding Fathers were not Deists and creatures of the (Liberal) Enlightenment, but rather Platonists. Drury notes that like postmodernists on the left, Straussians believe there is no ultimate truth, but that instead there are only discourses of power and that whoever controls the discourse wins. She notes that this is what makes American politics so narrow and so tedious -- the right and the left both operate from the same morally bankrupt premise.
This goes a long way toward explaining the bizarre combination of libertarianism and fundamentalism in neo-conservative thought. Like other dogmas which have been used to support those in power -- Social Darwinism and eugenics come to mind -- neoconservatism is just the latest apologia for the up-to-date reactionary. Notably, its adherents are generally unaware of the contradiction. This does not deter them from defending this instrumental hodgepodge of Ayn Rand "objectivism" and millenarian "revivalism" however. Such a philosophy is, of course, its own best self-satirization.
Well-written, its conclusions careful and amply defended, LEO STRAUSS AND THE AMERICAN RIGHT, is not the ravings of conspiracy theorist. It does not imagine that Straussians have come to run the United States, nor that they form a secret cult which pulls the strings behind the scene. It exposes rather the infiltration of post-modern intellectual cynicism into the once decent, and even honorable, Republican Party.
Strauss goes into the idea of "liberal education". Men who rely on education and modern philosophical principles alone to build a better society wind up following the path of Marx, i.e. Communism, and Nietzsche and Heidegger, i.e. Fascism. Strauss, in the aftermath of WWII, spends his life touting the virtues of classical philosophy as a way to turn back some of the harm done by modern philosophers. The reader comes away realizing that you need a mixture of both "rule of law" and "men of character" to build a good society. As a retired Army officer and student of political philosophy, I found this to be a great book to start one's journey into political philosophy.