Used price: $0.40
Collectible price: $1.50
Used price: $0.99
Collectible price: $15.00
http://www.parecon.org
On the other hand, the lunar mission was a sterling example of human achievement driven by rationality, the culmination of the application of brainpower to a problem, and the success which resulted therefrom. Oh certainly, Rand drew (and draws) a lot of fire, but she was absolutely correct in her belief that upgrades of our human condition will only be developed by people who think and act, and not by herds of hippies standing in the rain.
Consider the anarchists and socialists who arrive in jets at WTO meetings. Their main goal (apart from the ubiquitous violence) is an end to free trade and capitalism. (No word on what will replace a market system.) At the just completed conference on development, environmental groups protested such things as outdoor plumbing, electricity to villages in Africa and the idea of using credit instead of traditional ways (bartering goods). This in spite of all evidence that these things have made life easier and longer for 3rd world folks.
On another level, the Left is mounting a relentless, ideological assault at universities against any discussion of ideas it does not approve of and on those same campuse and in Europe, one witnesses a rising tide of virulent anti-semitism. Jews have always been connected with the financial side of capitalism which may explain some of the hatred. The problem with the "New Left" is that they view industrialism as predominantly a matter of workers engaging in manual tasks. The idea that physical abd not intellectual labor drives economies would be applicable in a pre-industrial society. And that, I guess, was the point of these essays - that what the New Left is asking for is anti-industrial in nature.
Yes, some of these essays stretch the point - but the idea of comparing unlike events to arrive at a stated conclusion is quite common. What this book does do is remind us that ideas have consequences in the real world. Prophetically, the article on public schools sounds as if it could have been written yesterday.
Used price: $20.95
Collectible price: $21.18
In the foreword, Mr. Robbins wastes no time in calling Rand's philosophy "deadly poison," then he attempts to "prove" his point using out-of-context quotes and word twisting. Let's look at one glaring example from the second chapter:
Mr. Robbins quotes Rand as saying that "reason" is "the faculty that identifies and integrates the material provided by man's senses." He then claims that she equivocated on the meaning of "reason" when she said that "reason is the only objective means of communication and understanding among men." This claim is absolutely ridiculous. The former quote is the definition of reason; the latter is a description of one of its many uses--there is no equivocation here.
Mr. Robbins makes the claim that "Christianity and Objectivism have no presuppositions or propositions in common. They have no common ground." Thank goodness that is not the case; for if it were, then Christianity would have no foundation. Is not the most basic presupposition of Objectivism that existence exists?
By inference one might conclude that Mr. Robbins does not believe in existence. But as president of the Trinity Foundation, he believes that one God exists in three Persons. If he really believes that Christianity and Objectivism have no common ground, then he is guilty of the fallacy of the stolen concept, for the concept of existence is necessary in order to believe that God exists.
That error in itself may be a simple oversight. Unfortunately, it is only the tip of the iceberg. In the final chapter of this book, Mr. Robbins introduces us to the philosophy of Gordon H. Clark, which he calls Scripturalism. Unfortunately, Scripturalism's epistemology is only workable if you first accept Objectivism's entire epistemology as a presupposition! Mr. Robbins makes the incredible claim that the Bible is the source of all knowledge. How are we to read and understand the Bible in the first place if we cannot engage in the very process of concept formation that is central to Objectivist epistemology?
While Mr. Robbins rightly pointed out some serious errors in the conclusions Rand came to, he failed in his chief aim, which was to destroy the foundation of Objectivism. I hope that anyone, and especially any Objectivists, who are unfortunate enough to read this book will also take a look at the works of Norman Geisler before drawing any conclusions about true Christianity.
Robbins updated and expanded that work in 1997 under the new name ,Without a Prayer. This book is certainly worth reading, but -- while it was one of the better discussions of Objectivism at the time -- it has been superseded by other works.
I must first object to the macabre cover. On the front of the work is Rand's tombstone and the back, that of her husband Frank O'Connor. What's the point?
In any event, the substance of this work isn't quite that bad. There are a couple of excellent chapters -- those dealing with her theory of concept formation and also the religious nature of Objectivism. Robbins has an eye for showing the contradictions and false assumptions of Objectivism, but at times he gives the least charitable interpretation of something Rand said to then contrast it with something else she said, in order to make Rand look silly or muddleheaded. Of course, Rand was these things at times, but not even she deserves to be unnecessarily held up to ridicule.
Some of the work is mediocre and at times borders on the scurrilous. For example, Robbins tells us that "Their [Christians] continued existence under Objectivist government has already been the subject of debate in Objectivist circles . . . ." [p. 210.] Of course, there is no citation to such a "debate." A society based on Objectivism certainly wouldn't be hospitable to the senile, the retarded, and anyone who doesn't agree with Rand. But to imply that Objectivists advocate the murder of Christians is to out-Rand Rand at her worst. While Mr. Robbins rightly protests that Leonard Peikoff wrongly equates the rise of Nazism with Christianity, he no has qualms of stooping to Peikoff's level (or worse) when he attacks Objectivism.
Robbins even gets silly when describing David Kelley as a "radio receiver channeling omnipresent energy." [p. 37 n. 25.] Rand said some foolish things in her day, but I don't recall reading anything so silly as that.
This book is to be commended on one ground, however. Mr. Robbins has no doubt introduced a great many people to the thought of Gordon Clark, one of the most influential apologists in recent history.
John W. Robbins is an intellectual UFO. A Christian, he discovered Ayn Rand while in college and, admiring her "uncompromising vision... of how the world might be and ought to be" and her "portrayals of rational, creative, and intransigeant individuals", he "read all that Rand published". Even today, he agrees with many of her positions, such as "her praise of purpose and productive work, her condemnation of lazinesss, her enthusiasm for private property, her advocacy of laissez-faire capitalism and limited government, her attacks on altruism, her support of egoism and her vigorous defense of logic."
However, Robbins is not an Objectivist, but a follower of evangelical Protestant philosopher Gordon H. Clark, some of whose shorter pieces are included in the appendices. Robbins defines Clark's philosophy as "scripturalism", a doctrine according to which "all our thoughts- there are no exceptions- are to be brought into conformity to Scripture, for all the treasures of wisdom and knowledge are contained in Scripture." Among the corollaries of this position are the idea that evolution is "the greatest superstition of the twentieth century", and an extremely negative (Popperian) view of science, according to which "all the laws of science are false, and all have the same probability: zero" because they are "conclusions of logically fallacious arguments".
In Objectivist terms, he is a pure intrinsicist: he believes that we have access to infallible propositional truths, which are delivered to us directly from the mind of God via Scripture, and that all our knowledge either comes directly from Revelation or from logical deductions from it. A pure rationalist, too, he totally rejects empirical evidence as a possible basis for knowledge, and reduces logic to deduction, denying even the possibility of induction ("Truth cannot be derived from something non-propositional, such as 'observations'. Unless one starts with propositions, one cannot end with propositions.")
Most people - and especially most Objectivists - would be tempted to dismiss him as a wacky fundamentalist, but I personally respect Christians and even admire some Catholics, and I even share some of Robbins' ethics and politics, so I was willing to listen.
Actually, *Ayn Rand and the Close of her System* contains excellent points against Objectivism, some of which I had already arrived at by my own thinking. I particularly liked, for instance, Robbins's argument that what the "primacy of existence" actually means is "the primacy of unconsciousness"; his identification of the bias inherent in the "indestructible robot" example used to justify the concept of life as the root of value (the robot is assumed to be impassible and unchangeable); or the argument that Rand's ethics would "seem to permit, if not require, murderers to fight against their just punishment" and is "completely compatible with a pro-death, pro-suicide point of view" - among many other highly interesting points.
I am not saying that Robbins has refuted Objectivism, only that some of his points corroborated or even refined my own understanding of the problems of the philosophy and raised objections I am currently unable to answer. Of course, not every argument is of a high caliber. Robbins occasionally resorts to ad hominem, sarcasm or straw man arguments. Moreover, even though he does understand many of the points he discusses, he is prey to a certain number of false alternatives, assuming for instance that the non-intrinsicist is necessarily a Kantian subjectivist or that a volitional theory of consciousness must necessarily exclude the possibility of automatic processes at all levels, including the sub-conscious.
In fact, if true, Robbins' critique would be devastating not only for Objectivism, but for modern science (including psychology and psychiatry, which he rejects as "pseudo-science" and "witchdoctory") and the whole empiricist tradition in philosophy. He is particularly virulent against Aristotle, whom, contrary to Rand who saw in him "the first of our Founding Fathers", he calls an "explicit totalitarian" and a "fascist". But Rand's interpretation is vindicated in such Objectivist works as Robert Mayhew's *Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Republic* or F. D. Miller's *Nature, Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics*. As for Robbins' attacks on the Objectivist politics, it seems to focus on rather careless statements of the theory, and might not be as effective against the more scholarly derivation of the Objectivist position in Tara Smith's *Moral Rights and Political Freedom*.
Even though Robbins' own point of view is untenable and he is not always a very nice person, I think his book is worthy of close scrutiny and deserves a systematic Objectivist answer.
Used price: $17.99
Buy one from zShops for: $13.94
But Nyquist goes on to mischaracterize Kelley's argument in this work (Kelley does not defend tolerance solely on the basis of the notion that evil deeds are the only thing that can make one evil; he agrees with Rand that it is intellectual dishonesty and evasion that make one, fundamentally, an immoral person). Later, Nyquist stakes out what I regard as a mistaken philosophical position. He approvingly quotes a very stupid idea from a very silly thinker (Popper), a thinker who did not realize that his own half-wit innovation on Logical Empiricism was susceptible to the very same criticisms that he made of Marx and Freud.
In any case, the idea of Popper's is this: all hell will break loose and liberalism be destroyed if we believe there are moral facts. Nyquist writes that: "If you believe, as all good Randites are supposed to believe, that 'reason' can discover objective moral absolutes that can be validated beyond all doubt, then I do not see how one can escape Peikoff's position that tolerance is essentially vicious." This is a ridiculous argument, as ridiculous applied to Kelley and Rand as it would be if applied to Christians or G.E.Moore. Whether or not the position that there are moral facts will lead logically to intolerance DEPENDS ON WHAT THE MORAL FACTS IN QUESTION ARE. If one of the moral facts is that one should listen to others and not condemn them as immoral on the basis of complicated intellectual errors that they might make by mistake, then the belief that this is a fact will not lead to intolerance. (This is precisely what Kelley holds.) In addition, Rand's morality is an individualistic, agent-relative morality, and if Peikoff realized this and gave up his semi-deontological characterizations of Rand's views, it would become increasingly apparent that the notion of getting all worked up over what other people do (when it has no chance of effecting you) is A SILLY WASTE OF TIME.
Granted, given certain ethical beliefs, holding that they are true MIGHT entail some kind of neo-fascist, coercive implementation of them. But this is not the case with Rand, as it is not the case with Christianity (the argument Nyquist outlines is often made against Christians).
So: Nyquist understands neither Rand's ethics nor Kelley's book, and I urge other readers to judiciously set his comments aside. Nyquist should leave philosophical commentary to the professionals.
...
But the gnostics won't read the book, because getting caught carrying a work by David Kelley in your backpack is sufficient cause for excommunication.
Kelley defends Objectivism as a philosophy of reason. Those who value it as such will find the book an excellent analysis of the inductive nature of judging character as well as the difference between error and evil. Those who value Objectivism as a kind of religion in which John Galt and Howard Roark are avatars and Leonard Peikoff is an oracle, would do well to wait for the Cliff Notes version. It will leave less of a bruise on their foreheads.
Well, then I read this book. It is many things: Kelley defends a view about what is essential (i.e., most fundamental) to Objectivism, and also what warrants being called Objectivist. He defends a view about the assessment of moral character. But for me - at the time - this book was an invaluable window into the weird, behind-the-scenes world of Objectivism. It was written as Kelley's defense in response to his "excommunication" by Peikoff, Binswanger, Schwartz, and others who run the official movement. Now, Kelley takes these people seriously, and he tries to answer their arguments and lay out the justification for the actions that got him excommunicated (he accepted an invitation to speak at the Laissez-Faire books dinner). But if one reads between the lines, one starts to see what is really going on. One gets a picture of how the Objectivist movement has been totally handicapped by hacks like Peikoff, Binswanger, and Schwartz, who want their followers to BELIEVE every word Ayn Rand said without thinking too hard about it. In short, it looks highly probable that these people had no real principled argument with Kelley (that's just a smokescreen). In reality, they were just jealous of Kelley's intellectual abilities, and (more importantly) they feared the honesty and openness of his intellectual work. "Wild," you might say, but no: it looks very probable that Peikoff, etc think that Kelley's openness - his willingness to say, "I don't know; that part of Objectivism hasn't really been developed," or "Well, there are a number of things you might think, here" - will destroy their little power-structure and money-making machine, the Ayn Rand Institute. Why? Because once people start saying, "Uh, gee, there really are some puzzles in Objectivist doctrine," people will start asking Peikoff and his associates questions. They won't be able to answer, and people will quit taking them so seriously (and be less likely to contribute). At the end of this book, one sees that Kelley was a threat to be contained - not a threat to Objectivist principle - a threat the Ayn Rand Institute's (ARI) support and revenues. It is now the official °RI policy that one should not even READ Kelley's book. Ah, now I understand. It is no wonder that such an infertile, incestuous, fear-regulated organization has produced no scholars of merit. No decent person could, in good conscience, stay on board at that place.
Used price: $16.50
I don't agree with many of Rands views, but just read Nyquists' reviews of all Randian literature to see just how biased he is.
human nature than Nyquist ?
The view of human beings that Nyquist develops with such a worldview is cynical, but Nyquist is obviously able to empathize with lofty ideals - he just thinks that all issues should be brought to the bar of scientific and rational analysis with substantiating evidence. Of course, he also stresses that you should not evade the evidence contrary to your theme.
How well does Nyquist's criticism of Objectivism hit its mark when shooting from this perspective? It hits it very well! Nyquist criticizes Objectivist claims about human nature, history, art and philosophy by simply taking an Objectivist position, looking for the evidence, and asking what science, and then his philosophical viewpoint, have to say on the matter. My favorite parts of his critique are his criticisms of Rand's assertions about human nature and the tabula rasa mind. I had thought about doing such a critique myself, but guessed intuitively that Nyquist would have done one first. He presents the empirically based genetic and sociobiological evidence for genetic influences on human choices and behavior.
I am not a history buff, so I am not able to critique historical views with great competence. While Nyquist might score points here, I think it might have helped if he was able to cite more than one reference for every point that he made, or at least, primary references. However, this does not destroy his points that undermine the lazy approach of replacing real empirically tested or substantiated knowledge with philosophical perspectives.
While I disagree with Nyquist's arguments that attempt to dissociate logic from metaphysics (I am acquainted with the history of the argument between Blanshard and Nagel on that point - not directly presented by Nyquist - and I side with Blanshard), I do appreciate and agree with his argument that the scientific claims pretty much trump speculative philosophical ones and that underlying philosophies that declare allegiance to "reason" are not necessarily declaring an allegiance to the scientific method that certifies predictive and testable knowledge. I also agree with him that it is when allegiance to *scientific empiricism* is pervasive, and not just *bland declarations of allegiance to reason* that progress amongst human beings is greatest (not that the two are totally mutally exclusive, but Newton is an example of a mystic who was a scientific empiricist). Speculative philosophy can be right about things, but the idea that it grants certain knowledge is very dubious, whether coming from Objectivism, Christianity or Marxism. The method by which of verbalist speculation replaces science is common in lots of philosophy. Nyquist uses this to show how Rand ends up confusing many of her readers by playing upon their intuitive understandings of her ambiguously defined words. He does what is pretty clear to most people who have argued with Objectivists - show that "reason" to a hardcore Objectivist is synonymous with "the ideas of Objectivism".
I do not think Nyquist has written a perfect book - I sometimes found the presentation format to be uneven (not every chapter seemed to have a conclusion, for example), and there were points on which his disrespect for a certain position led him to dismiss it without sufficient empathy.
However, he deserves a 5-star review if only for bringing Objectivism to the bar of empirical analysis. Reviews that disagree with him will tend to dislike his naturalism, especially as he cynically applies it to ethics and politics, asking how Rand's capitalist fantasies, with which he (and I) share some sympathies, will ever take root.
In the end, you respect for this book will depend on whether you are able to empathize with arguments you disagree with, and whether your view of human nature is conserative or libertine.
Used price: $1.87
Collectible price: $9.53
Used price: $3.99
Collectible price: $8.85
Dr. Peikoff's theme is that actions follow from ideas. With passionate dedication to truth he quotes from the writings and speeches of the principle architects of Nazi Germany to show the ethical premises guiding their political actions and programs. The evidence is clearly presented. And it leads inexorably to the conclusion that the same ideas which made possible the horror that was Nazi Germany, currently dominates the intellectual establishment of the United States.
"The Ominous Parallels" is both a warning and an alert. It tells us what we should do to avoid becoming a fascist state. It alerts us to how far down that road we currently are.
Dr. Peikoff's "The Ominous Parallels" is also a rallying point for all of us who care deeply about the future of our country and the freedom of its citizens. It helps us to recognize that "it could happen here" if we do not change our views regarding the proper beneficiary of one's actions.
Used price: $4.95
Collectible price: $42.35
Rand was, in essence, a reactionary. She reacted -- and with good reason -- to the 1960s and 1970s, a rather insane period in our time. She makes some excellent points in "Apollo and Dionysis," contrasting the amazing human achievement of the Moon landing with the mud-wallowing revelry of Woodstock.
But venomous polemics do not "reason" make. In the world of Randians, all is black and white. Balance does not exist. Either you are are an Apollonian creature of the mind -- a faceless John Galt -- or you're a craven Dionysian carouser. (Rand never figured out how to, as Hunter Thompson wrote, "wallow with the eagles at night and fly with the pigs in the morning.")
This maddening tendency toward judgment leaches from every essay in this collection.... and is the prime reason why I can't give it a much better rating.
Page after page reveals profound insights into the intellectual atmosphere of the times. The writing is always informative and thought provoking, and quite often brilliant.
In short, this volume is especially suitable for readers already familiar with the gist of Ayn Rand's philosophy and literary writing.
For starters, Yang has understood Objectivism very well indeed. In this book, he gives quotation after quotation from Rand and her followers. He spells out the Objectivist position before he criticizes her and demonstrates her flawed thinking. Over 700 footnote citations and about 100 works cited in the bibliography are evidence of his meticulous effort. Furthermore, Yang consistently begins by presenting an empathetic view of Objectivism, especially in the early chapters, with respect to its beliefs about self-esteem, romantic love, and productive work. Gradually, he reveals the internal contradictions in Rand's views and then shows that Rand could not justify her ideals on the basis of her premises. And it was Rand who challenged readers: "Check your premises."
As for taking an uncritical view of the Bible and failing to account for the manuscript evidence, that accusation fails considering Yang's gargantuan effort to critically discuss Christianity and Objectivism in 367 pages. Furthermore, Yang's primary objective in his book was not the question of manuscript evidence for the Bible. One of his objectives seems to have been to point out the failure of the philosophical empiricism and materialism of Rand and contrast it with Christian revelation. Nevertheless, Yang gives a page-long footnote discussion on page 348 on the subject of manuscript evidence and offers some suggestions for further reading.
As to the subject of science, such as the question of an empirical proof for the existence of God, one would do well to read Yang's chapter on epistemology (Reason and Reality) or his chapter on Science and Christianity; (this last chapter of 55 some pages could easily have stood alone as a monograph on the subject). These chapters marshal the writings of scientists as well as non-Christian philosophers of science like Stephen Hawking, Karl Popper, Thomas Kuhn, Imre Lakotos and others, to demonstrate the logical fallacies that are at the heart of the scientific method and reveal the utter skepticism that results from adopting an empirical philosophy. This leads to the intriguing conclusion: if science can't prove anything at all, it is begging the question to require Christianity to prove its veracity by the method of science. As to the issue of Creation and the question of the speed of light slowing down leading to the illusion of a older universe, a previous reader also seems to have misread Yang. Yang had already demonstrated that one problem with the scientific method was that an infinite number of hypotheses can "fit" the finite number of empirical, observed "facts". Although the belief in divine creation does not require that one knows for certain that the speed of light is slowing down; nevertheless, the slowing of the speed of light, as documented in a standard college physics textbook, supports one hypothesis, namely that the universe is much younger than we have been told it is. By the same token, it contradicts the theory of evolution and the idea of an ancient universe. Yang is merely taking one empirical finding of physics and using it against those who would utilize science to argue against the Christian belief in creation. He did not assert that the slowing of the speed of light is a certainty or that it was the basis of his belief in creation. How could he? He denies, along with reputable philosophers of science, that science can produce truth.
Rand's literary abilities were considerable, but her philosophy had numerous flaws, which unfortunately, many of her admirers have ignored. This excellent book by a former Rand admirer has shown us where the problems lie and discussed them honestly and thoughtfully. Moreover, this work takes readers beyond Rand's writings and challenges them to consider some broader philosophical issues. It is well worth the time and the money.
Used price: $16.93
Buy one from zShops for: $16.95
She is not a serious Aristotelian, she is just another atheist philosopher...a dime a dozen.
St. Thomas Aquinas was a serious Aristotelian. If there is any doubt let us look at his genius. Aquinas could remember EVERYTHING ever said to him by anyone and recall EVERY word that he ever read. His single-ness of mind and genius is further demonstrated by the fact that he could write (at least) three different books at the same time by dictating to 3 different secretaries seated around him, and going from concepts in one book to different concepts in another book, instantly and without any difficulty of mind.
Rand's philosophy is hiddenly close-minded. That is, it appears to be open-minded and "truth loving," but is not. She is a "corner painter." Her level of intelligence is certainly high, but Aquinas would run intellectual circles around her head. She was not at that level of genius.
OK, let's make it simpler:
So, who would you rather hear perform Strauss' "Death and Transfiguration"? The Chicago Symphony Orchestra or the Lubjawana Radio Symphony Orchestra? Answer is easy: Chicago.
Aquinas or Rand? Answer is easy: Aquinas. Anyday.
Oh, I have one final thought for you. Rand is trying to explain that God can't exist because He cannot fit into our concept of nature, with all it's finite limitations. That is tantamount to saying that a Ford Taurus cannot exist because it can't fit into a cardboard box. Unfortunately, death overcame her before she could figure that one out. Tisk, tisk.
Now, I am not convinced that Long has gotten it right, but he certainly states some well-formulated doubts about Objectivism. The other two writers in the volume - Fred Miller and Eyal Mozes - try to resist Long's arguments, but they do not state their views precisely and clearly enough (but hey, they didn't get as much space to write in as Long). Any serious Objectivist will want to think about how to respond to Long's arguments philosophically. And by the way: this guy is no hack. This book ...is probably the best piece of serious, non-hostile, informed critical work on Objectivism ever written. This book is *SO* much better than these critical works written by mystics, Christians, and egalitarian socialists; the writer is a serious Aristotelian, . ...
Amazingly enough, the author easily commands an intellect far greater than those his book is about, combined! I sleep with this book at night...
if you know what I mean.