Used price: $8.49
Buy one from zShops for: $9.89
Used price: $23.81
Collectible price: $31.76
Buy one from zShops for: $23.00
I also recommend: Stroud, Quest; Brewer, Perception and Reason; McDowell, Mind and World. Boghossian, New Essays on Apriori...
While my own incliniation is towards a sceptically grounded naturalistic solution to the sceptical paradox, and I find McGinn's attempts to sketch a dispositional account to be highly flawed (refer to the huge amount of secondary literature for the arguments), the real value of the work is the extremely lucid and well-argued exposition of Wittgenstein's main concerns in the Philosophical Investigations, together with the critique of the Kripke interpretation.
Used price: $17.89
Buy one from zShops for: $17.89
This text is a decent overview of these topics, eps. on Frege, Russell, and Kripke. The most interesting chs. are on necessity and existence (Soames is the authority on truth).
McGinn argues in favor of existence in terms of a first-order predicate (as opposed to quantificational paraphrase) and rejects identity in strictly quantifiable terms (via Leibniz's law). He sees identity as a primitive relation expressed by a 2-place predicate, which is his take off stance on necessity (possible worlds). At bottom, McGinn rejects a philosopher's 'infatuation' with expressions of modality as strictly quantificational. One may find interest in his arguments for such a rejection.
Caution: it is not for an audience unfamiliar with college level philosophy, but neither is it exceedingly complex.
I place McGinn up there with Hume as a stylist and philosopher.
Used price: $2.40
That's not to say that a philosophically-minded person has no reason to read this book. McGinn's perspectives on abortion, sex, drugs, etc. are certainly worth reading and will stimulate thought in any reader.
McGinn's thinking is heavily influenced by virtue ethics, which disappointed me, but I hear that a lot of people go for that sort of thing.
List price: $25.95 (that's 30% off!)
Used price: $3.74
Collectible price: $13.50
Buy one from zShops for: $5.99
All too often, philosophers write in an arcane, esoteric language baffling to laypersons untrained in the discipline. The layperson's reaction to reading such perceived mumbo-jumbo is typically "Say what?" or "So what?"
In The Making of a Philosopher, Colin McGinn seeks to rescue philosophy from its ivory tower, bring it down to earth, and explain it in an accessible, engaging way. He is only partially successful; some sections of his book remain tough sledding.
McGinn, 52, was born in West Hartlepool, county Durham, a small mining town in the northeast of England. He was educated at the Univ. of Manchester and Oxford Univ. He now lives in New York City and is a Professor of Philosophy at Rutgers.
An analytical philosopher dealing with language and logic, McGinn traces his philosophical lineage from Plato and Aristotle, through Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Descartes, Leibniz, and Kant, to Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein--a tradition that emphasizes clarity, rigor, argument, theory, and truth.
"It is not a tradition," he writes, "that aims primarily for inspiration or consolation or ideology. Nor is it particurlary concerned with 'philosophy of life"--though parts of it are. This kind of philosophy is more like science than religion, more like mathematics than poetry--though it is neither science nor mathematics."
As an academic philosopher, McGinn has been interested mainly in epistemology, linguistic analysis, and cognitive science. Alas, in The Making of a Philosopher, he does not even mention my two favorite philosophers, Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, nor does he deal with Eastern philosophy, other representatives of Continental philosophy, or post-modern philosophy.
McGinn is probably best known as the author of a provocative essay, "Can the Mind-Body Problem Be Solved?" (which is by far the most cited, reprinted, and translated paper he has ever written). His answer to this question is no. "We aren't god, after all," he writes; "we are recently evolved organisms made of pretty low-tech materials. Our human intelligence is not cut out for the job" [of solving such knotty problems.
"Maybe the human species cannot be expected to understand," he writes, "how the universe contains mind and matter in combination. Isn't it really a preposterous overconfidence on our part to think that our species--so recent, so contingent, so limited in many ways--can nevertheless unlock every secret of the natural world?"
In my opinion, the "linguistic turn" that characterized 20th-century philosophy was unfortunate, leading to a dry, dreary, and dull wasteland. And, apparently, McGinn himself would agree. After spending many years as an analytic philosopher, he has now turned his energies to connecting philosophical concepts with "real life" and making philosophy accessible to educated laypersons.
In discussing metaphilosophy--the philosophy of philosophy--McGinn points out that philosophy is not an exact science and can never attain the certainty of mathematics or the clarity of logic. The closer we get to philosophy, the more problematical it becomes.
"Philosophy must now be admitted," he writes, "to be a condition of terminal puzzlement, a permanent fretting ignorance." One should not be daunted or discouraged, however, by this insight, for as Socrates always maintained, it is the wise man who knows his own ignorance.
The Making of a Philosopher is a candid work revealing that philosophy can be a passionate and exciting pursuit. Writing with intelligence and humor, the author pulls no punches concerning the strong and weak points of his chosen field. And the narrative flows smoothly: not many academic philosophers can write this well.
Colin McGinn is the author of thirteen previous books, including The Mysterious Flame, The Character of Mind, The Problem of Consciousness, and Ethics, Evil, and Fiction.
But that's not the thrill of McGinn's book. The thrill is that he was born into a family of British coal miners with the mind of a genius. The story of how he makes his way through a provincial university (in psychology), and then to Oxford, and finally to Rutgers and the world's leading philosophy department is pure Horatio Alger, except that it's told entirely in terms of the IDEAS that McGinn became absorbed in at the different stages of his philosophical development. Since he's the world's clearest writer, anybody can understand these problems and ideas -- it's like being given a personal tour of 20th century philosophy by a guide who can make you understand every philsophical problem and position as well as if you had his own mind.
The only parts of the book I had reservations about were the early section of McGinn's infatuation with Bertrand Russell, whom I consider a reptile as a person and simply shallow and "clever" as a philosopher, and the section at the end where he takes to dropping names of movie actresses and opera singers he's gotten to know since he became famous. One wants to believe that someone with a mind like McGinn's has a little more austere sense of self than this People magazine bedazzlement with empty-headed celebrities. (He mocks himself for all this name-dropping, but that doesn't help matters.)
But those are tiny reservations. If you want a first-rate course in 20th century philosophy that reads like a detective story, you should buy this book and read it and reread it. (I've now read it three times.) The decision to embed philsophical problems and analysis in the narrative of a young working-class Brit's rise from the mining pits to the heights of 21st century philosophy was brilliant. This is as close as non-philosophers will every get to what top-level analytic philosophy looks and feels like from the inside.
Used price: $20.37
Used price: $9.00
Buy one from zShops for: $1.56
Mcginns theory, in an nutshell is that, while we can view the brain only from outside, we, at least so far, have only been able to see the mind from the inside. From this, he concludes that we can not connect the two views i.e., even if we know that certain neural patterns cause certain sensations, this only explains THAT there is a particular connection, not HOW those neurons create the sensation. The middle ground needed to transition the two views, Mcginn argues, is inaccessable to human consciousness.
It is here that Mcginn takes it too far, even though he is correct to remind us that we've no reason to expect that every concievable question has an answer accessable to human consciousness. He even reminds us that, as evolutionary creatures, our minds, like every other organ, were evolved to solve our ancestors problems. Why, from that standpoint, should we then expect that the human mind is capable of understanding itself? My answer would be that just as we have no reason to suspect that we can successfully answer the problem, we have no reason to suspect that we can't.
To make matters worse, explaining the theory the first time is not good enough. With slight variation, every chapter restates his theory with equal vigor. Even the discussions of the sections dispelling pansychism and dualism (with and without god) are given short treatment in favor of correspondingly lengthy explanations of why Mcginns theory is to be favored.
What good I can say is that this book is probably one of the best intros to tht philosophy of mind outside of Pinkers "How the Mind Works" and Dennett and Hofstadter's "The Minds I." For the more experienced, Read Mcginns (and for counterpoint, John Searle's) academic work.
Used price: $8.95
Buy one from zShops for: $10.00