Nevertheless, despite these criticisms, I urge all those who are interested in art to read the book, regardless of what they think of Rand. The book is written on a much higher level than most pro-Rand books that are published nowadays. Torres and Kamhi, unlike Rand's orthodox disciples, at least are sound scholars with an appreciation for empirical evidence and close logical analysis. They are fair to opposing viewpoints (unlike Rand herself, who treated opponents as if they were sub-human), and they provide an excellent overview of the excesses of modern and post-modern art. Merely as a phillipic against bad art (or, as the authors would insist, "non-art"), I would give this book a five star rating. But because of the methodological essentialism, I have to drop it down to four. The emphasis on definitions really can get annoying.
Used price: $10.00
Collectible price: $25.50
Used price: $9.92
Collectible price: $10.95
Instead, T&K offer a pretentious (and at times inaccurate) account of Ayn Rand's esthetic theory with a critique that offers neither any good reasons to accept her theory nor any good reasons to reject it.
T&K devote the first 55 pages of their 539-page work to recount the theory that Rand presented in the first 64 pages of "The Romantic Manifesto" (a work whose style and tone lives up to that title-a manifesto). A typical passage from T&K goes like this: (quoting AR's statement on the artistic significance of a painting including a cold sore on the lip of a beautiful woman) "[that minor affliction] acquires a monstrous metaphysical significance by virtue of being included in a painting. It declares that a woman's beauty and her efforts to achieve glamor (the beautiful evening gown) are a futile illusion undercut by a seed of corruption which can mar and destroy them at any moment-that this is reality's mockery of man-that all of man's values and efforts are impotent against the power, not even of some great cataclysm, but of a miserable little physical infection." To which T&K obliquely add, "particular details do assume greater significance in a work of art than they would possess in reality, because the viewer is at least subliminally aware that their presence is intentional, and that the artist must therefore have considered them important" (T&K, 49).
Interspersed throughout such banal commentary is T&K's critique-or, more exactly, their quibbles (a critique is at least coherent), which consist chiefly of reading Rand either in the most concrete-bound or most exaggerated way possible and then criticizing her for being concrete-bound or exaggerated. An example of their context-switching gimmick can be seen in their repeated quibble that Rand misuses the term "entity." As she made clear in ITOE (264-276), Rand uses the term (as everybody does) in two senses: in a primary sense, to refer to physical, coherent objects (e.g., a ball), and in an extended sense, to refer to anything that exists (e.g., a thought). Whenever a term is used in two senses, there is the danger of equivocation. But T&K variously criticize Rand for using the term strictly in the primary sense (61), or in the extended sense (336n23), but not in both senses simultaneously (62)! How can Rand win? T&K use the same gimmick in their complaints about Rand's use of the term "Romanticism" (31-33), which is variously meant as an era in art history and as an approach to art. Thus, when Rand uses the term to describe as approach to art, they scold her for being anachronistic, and when she uses the term to describe as era, they reproach her for seeing an approach that doesn't exist. Their gimmick becomes the most absurd when they claim that Rand is a psychological determinist (41), an argument that not only relies on switching the senses in her use of the word "determine," but also in quoting Rand out of context (thereby managing a context-switching, context-dropping twofer).
If the criticisms of Rand's theory weren't bad enough, T&K's support for her theory was even worse. Note that Rand's theory rises and falls on her contention that art serves a cognitive need-i.e., to objectify fundamental value-judgments-and that the fulfillment of this need provides art with its emotional power. According to T&K, Rand's theory, unlike others', is "informed by a more accurate understanding of human cognition and emotion"(16). Presumably, then, we would learn how this is the case. Unfortunately, for the next 93 pages, T&K support this contention solely by offering corroborating claims by pop psychologist Nathaniel Branden (who was Rand's student for many years) and clinical psychologist Edith Packer (who is also a Rand follower), neither of whom cite any relevant empirical support aside from inference and anecdote. Moreover, T&K's (very short) chapter "Scientific Support for Rand's Theory" only makes matters worse by uncritically recounting the *conclusions* of well-known neuropsychologists and anthropologists (such as Oliver Sacks and Ellen Dissanayake) without presenting enough evidence to allow the reader to judge for himself. Thus, the critical support that Rand's theory requires is supplanted with scientific window-dressing (just as T&K window-dress with more than 200 pages of footnotes and appendices!).
Window-dressing, I suppose, is a harmless past-time to amuse the rubes in Poughkeepsie, but T&K are also nasty. Throughout their work, they feel compelled to take unsubstantiated swipes at Rand and many other important Rand scholars, such as Leonard Peikoff and Harry Binswanger. These smears (like much of T&K's hopelessly self-indulgent editorializing) are not only unjust but appear especially absurd alongside the incredible fawning over Chris Sciabarra's work (proclaiming Rand to be Hegelian).
According to Gotthelf's "On Ayn Rand," "[t]here is, unfortunately, not much serious interpretive value among the secondary material that has been published on Ayn Rand in books or academic journals to date." Despite the importance of their subject, T&K have done nothing to change this assessment-either of material on Rand or esthetics.